I have decided to start this thread so that I can refer to it in other threads, giving one place for this topic, so that when it comes up, I don't need to post this over and over again and derail some other threads. Of course, we can discuss this topic in this thread, and as far as I am concerned, if the thread is over 30 days old, it is okay with me to revive it. However, you may wish to check with those who run this site for how they feel about reviving it.
Now to the topic at hand:
There is an issue of how one goes from statements of fact ("is" statements) to statements of value ("ought" statements), or whether there is any way to derive one from the other. I am going to present the standard interpretation of what David Hume had to say on this, and then explain why I believe that that is wrong, both in the sense of being a mistaken interpretation of what Hume meant, and also that the idea of the standard interpretation is also wrong and ought not be believed. The standard interpretation of what David Hume had to say about this is as follows, which I quote in order to avoid accusations of misrepresentation:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Is–ought_problem
So, according to the standard interpretation, it is impossible to legitimately derive morals from statements of fact. In other words, that one cannot derive an 'ought' from an 'is.'
It will be useful to take a look at the paragraph in which the issue is raised, to see the exact words of Hume:
http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/342#Hume_0213_1007
The occurs in The Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, Part I, Section 1, last paragraph.
The first thing to observe is the fact that Hume did not actually state that it is impossible to derive morals ('ought statements') from matters of fact ('is statements'). His exact words are, with added emphasis:
That something seems inconceivable is very different from something being inconceivable. If Hume had wanted to say that it was inconceivable, he could have done so. But in fact, he did not.
Also, this is a tacked-on paragraph ("I cannot forbear adding...") at the end of a section, not presented as anything essential to his thinking.
It is also worth mentioning that the idea that an 'ought' statement cannot be derived from an 'is' statement is something for which an argument should be presented, and not something that should just be accepted without reason. The fact that Hume presents no reason to accept that idea fits better with the idea that he never meant such a thing, than with the idea that he did. It is also rather interesting that many who interpret Hume in accordance with the standard interpretation often accept it as being true, without any argument.
Sometimes, though, people mean something other than what they say, as, for example, it would have been unwise to publicly proclaim atheism in Hume's day, and so one might naturally expect someone to avoid explicitly saying such a thing, even if it were true. But, in fact, Hume explicitly stated that morals could be derived from matters of fact. Ironically, in the paragraph immediately prior to the famous one quoted above. Here it is, with the relevant part with added emphasis:
So here we have Hume explicitly stating that moral judgements are matters of fact. It would be a very strange thing if Hume meant to say, in the very next paragraph, that moral judgements are so disconnected from matters of fact, that one could not derive a moral statement from matters of fact.
Furthermore, Book III of the Treatise is about morals, and this occurs in the introductory portion of it, right before he spends the rest of the book deriving morals from statements of fact. (Book I of the Treatise is "Of the Understanding", about epistemology, and Book II is "Of the Passions".) Additionally, in Hume's later book, an Enquiry Concerning the Principle of Morals, he also derives 'ought' statements from 'is' statements. It would be very strange, indeed, if Hume meant to say that such things were impossible, when he spent so much time doing it himself.
Additionally, the Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals is a retelling of his ethical theory, and there is no retelling of the famous paragraph in which Hume allegedly made the claim that one cannot go from an 'is' to an 'ought.' That should tell everyone how unimportant that paragraph was to Hume's philosophy. In other words, he never meant the standard interpretation.
Of course, I do not expect people who are invested in the standard interpretation to change their minds. But the simple fact is, he never said what they claim he claimed, and the things he did claim are inconsistent with the standard interpretation.
What he meant was that when examining ethical theories, it is important to carefully look at the first stage where 'ought' statements appear, to see exactly how they are purportedly derived. In doing so, one will expose the "vulgar" theories, or, in other words, the bad theories that do not work.
Anyone who imagines that one cannot go from an is to an ought, should give us reason to believe their claim. Just claiming it without any argument is simply begging the question.
As for the claim itself, if there really were no connection between what is and what ought to be, what ought to be would not be anything at all.
Now to the topic at hand:
There is an issue of how one goes from statements of fact ("is" statements) to statements of value ("ought" statements), or whether there is any way to derive one from the other. I am going to present the standard interpretation of what David Hume had to say on this, and then explain why I believe that that is wrong, both in the sense of being a mistaken interpretation of what Hume meant, and also that the idea of the standard interpretation is also wrong and ought not be believed. The standard interpretation of what David Hume had to say about this is as follows, which I quote in order to avoid accusations of misrepresentation:
Quote:The is–ought problem, as articulated by Scottish philosopher and historian David Hume (1711–76), states that many writers make claims about what ought to be on the basis of statements about what is. Hume found that there seems to be a significant difference between descriptive statements (about what is) and prescriptive or normativestatements (about what ought to be), and that it is not obvious how one can coherently move from descriptive statements to prescriptive ones. The is–ought problem is also known as Hume's law and Hume's guillotine.
A similar though distinct view is defended by G. E. Moore's open-question argument, intended to refute any identification of moral properties with natural properties. This so-called naturalistic fallacy stands in contrast to the views of ethical naturalists.
...
Hume calls for caution against such inferences in the absence of any explanation of how the ought-statements follow from the is-statements. But how exactly can an "ought" be derived from an "is"? The question, prompted by Hume's small paragraph, has become one of the central questions of ethical theory, and Hume is usually assigned the position that such a derivation is impossible.[2] This complete severing of "is" from "ought" has been given the graphic designation of Hume's Guillotine.[3]
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Is–ought_problem
So, according to the standard interpretation, it is impossible to legitimately derive morals from statements of fact. In other words, that one cannot derive an 'ought' from an 'is.'
It will be useful to take a look at the paragraph in which the issue is raised, to see the exact words of Hume:
Quote:I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may, perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark’d, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surpriz’d to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ’tis necessary that it shou’d be observ’d and explain’d; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, [470]that this small attention wou’d subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason.
http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/342#Hume_0213_1007
The occurs in The Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, Part I, Section 1, last paragraph.
The first thing to observe is the fact that Hume did not actually state that it is impossible to derive morals ('ought statements') from matters of fact ('is statements'). His exact words are, with added emphasis:
Quote:For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ’tis necessary that it shou’d be observ’d and explain’d; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it.
That something seems inconceivable is very different from something being inconceivable. If Hume had wanted to say that it was inconceivable, he could have done so. But in fact, he did not.
Also, this is a tacked-on paragraph ("I cannot forbear adding...") at the end of a section, not presented as anything essential to his thinking.
It is also worth mentioning that the idea that an 'ought' statement cannot be derived from an 'is' statement is something for which an argument should be presented, and not something that should just be accepted without reason. The fact that Hume presents no reason to accept that idea fits better with the idea that he never meant such a thing, than with the idea that he did. It is also rather interesting that many who interpret Hume in accordance with the standard interpretation often accept it as being true, without any argument.
Sometimes, though, people mean something other than what they say, as, for example, it would have been unwise to publicly proclaim atheism in Hume's day, and so one might naturally expect someone to avoid explicitly saying such a thing, even if it were true. But, in fact, Hume explicitly stated that morals could be derived from matters of fact. Ironically, in the paragraph immediately prior to the famous one quoted above. Here it is, with the relevant part with added emphasis:
Quote:Nor does this reasoning only prove, that morality consists not in any relations, that are the objects of science; but if examin’d, will prove with equal certainty, that it consists not in any matter of fact, which can be discover’d by the understanding. This is the second part of our argument; and if it can be made evident, we may conclude, that morality is not an object of reason. But can there be any difficulty in proving, that vice and virtue are not matters of fact, whose existence we can infer by reason? Take any action allow’d to be vicious: Wilful murder, for instance. Examine it in all lights, and see if you can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In which-ever way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives, volitions and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. You never can find it, till you turn your reflexion into your [469]own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but ’tis the object of feeling, not of reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So that when you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. Vice and virtue, therefore, may be compar’d to sounds, colours, heat and cold, which, according to modern philosophy, are not qualities in objects, but perceptions in the mind: And this discovery in morals, like that other in physics, is to be regarded as a considerable advancement of the speculative sciences; tho’, like that too, it has little or no influence on practice. Nothing can be more real, or concern us more, than our own sentiments of pleasure and uneasiness; and if these be favourable to virtue, and unfavourable to vice, no more can be requisite to the regulation of our conduct and behaviour.
So here we have Hume explicitly stating that moral judgements are matters of fact. It would be a very strange thing if Hume meant to say, in the very next paragraph, that moral judgements are so disconnected from matters of fact, that one could not derive a moral statement from matters of fact.
Furthermore, Book III of the Treatise is about morals, and this occurs in the introductory portion of it, right before he spends the rest of the book deriving morals from statements of fact. (Book I of the Treatise is "Of the Understanding", about epistemology, and Book II is "Of the Passions".) Additionally, in Hume's later book, an Enquiry Concerning the Principle of Morals, he also derives 'ought' statements from 'is' statements. It would be very strange, indeed, if Hume meant to say that such things were impossible, when he spent so much time doing it himself.
Additionally, the Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals is a retelling of his ethical theory, and there is no retelling of the famous paragraph in which Hume allegedly made the claim that one cannot go from an 'is' to an 'ought.' That should tell everyone how unimportant that paragraph was to Hume's philosophy. In other words, he never meant the standard interpretation.
Of course, I do not expect people who are invested in the standard interpretation to change their minds. But the simple fact is, he never said what they claim he claimed, and the things he did claim are inconsistent with the standard interpretation.
What he meant was that when examining ethical theories, it is important to carefully look at the first stage where 'ought' statements appear, to see exactly how they are purportedly derived. In doing so, one will expose the "vulgar" theories, or, in other words, the bad theories that do not work.
Anyone who imagines that one cannot go from an is to an ought, should give us reason to believe their claim. Just claiming it without any argument is simply begging the question.
As for the claim itself, if there really were no connection between what is and what ought to be, what ought to be would not be anything at all.
"A wise man ... proportions his belief to the evidence."
— David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Section X, Part I.