(March 15, 2017 at 12:38 am)Nonpareil Wrote:
NonPareil,
I'm addressing this to you, because you do seem interested in actually discussing the argument. There are a number of atheist and also unfortunately Christians who argue it, and clearly don't even understand the syntax being used. For instance up until recently, I largely ignored it, because I thought that possible worlds was speculation about the multiverse.
First I was curious about your referenceing ipse dixit in regards to premise 3 and citing Plantinga as conceding this. I would just like to see it in context.
I found the following commentary on the discussion, and I wanted to get your opinion: http://www.randyeverist.com/2012/01/moda...ument.html
It uses the modal form of the argument that I have normally heard used
Quote: It is possible that a maximally great being exists.
2. If it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then a maximally great being exists in some possible world.
3. If a maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
4. If it exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world.
5. Therefore, a maximally great being exists.
What I found interesting was the conclusion
Quote:So it seems the crucial premise is the first one. Epistemically, one may say it is possible God does exist and possible he does not. However, we are interested in metaphysical possibility. It is on these grounds one must object. That objection can come in two forms: A. The concept of a maximally great being is incoherent,[2] or B. We do not (and/or cannot) know whether or not the concept of a maximally great being is metaphysically possible. With respect to (B), it’s not at all clear why we cannot justifiably intuit such a being is metaphysically possible (even if it’s not epistemologically compulsory that we do). With respect to (A), it seems the maximum values of what we would call “great-making” properties are coherent, and hence it follows they are metaphysically possible.[
John Feinberg, a Christian theologian, remarks on his interest in the ontological argument but seems to show agreement with its critics. He wrote, “what . . . [the ontological argument] proved is that a contingent being could not be God. Any being worthy of the title ‘God’ must be a necessary being.”[4] The philosophical rub Feinberg seemed not to catch, however, was this: in modal logic, a being or truth that is necessarily true means it is impossible not to exist. A necessary corollary or entailment of some being or truth being necessary is that if it does turn out to be false, it is necessarily so. So the MOA demonstrating the maximally great being’s necessary existence does more than give us a curious fact. Rather, it establishes that God’s existence is either necessary or impossible. Either the maximally great being is possible or impossible. This is why it is such a great argument!
I hate to quote so much, but this is closest to my view, and this author says what I mean in a much clearer way. I have also heard William Lane Craig mention a similar two conclusions to the argument but he didn't discuss the why of the "not possible conclusion" very well (so I didn't give it much though) I do think that there could be some issues with this view, but they reside else ware, and don't impact the logic or premise's of the argument itself.
Anyway... curious as to your thoughts, and to have a discussion concerning this.